The Austrian School is. Jesus Huerta De Soto

Austrian school of marginalism

For non-specialists, it should be clarified that economic knowledge until the end of the 19th century, they constituted one direction, today called classical political economy, which, with the advent of Marxist political economy, began to be divided (in general) into TWO currents. The concept of class struggle and the prediction of the finiteness of capitalism proposed by Karl Marx did not suit many other political economists, but the attitude towards the theory of labor value became the final watershed. The success of Karl Marx stimulated many other economists to write their "Anti-Capital" (See A. Marshall), and the general anti-Marxist the current formed several different economic schools, however, which, due to a common platform and omnivorousness, formed modern economics, called neoclassical economic theory.

20.05.2017 Material Austrian school from - the free encyclopedia

Austrian school(Also viennese school, psychological school) is a theoretical direction of economic science within the framework of marginalism, emphasizing the role of the self-organizing force of the market price mechanism. The basis of this approach is the assertion that the complexity of human behavior and the constantly changing nature of markets makes mathematical modeling in the economy extremely difficult (if not impossible). In this situation in the area economic policy the principles of free economy (Laissez-faire), economic liberalism and libertarianism become the main ones. followers of the Austrian school stand for the protection of freedom of contracts concluded by market participants (economic agents), and non-interference in transactions (especially by the state).

Austrian School of Economics Doctrine

Features of the Austrian school

  • refusal to use mathematical research methods;
  • subjectivism as characteristic almost all representatives of the school;
  • emphasis on the study of the psychological characteristics of consumer behavior;
  • emphasis on the structure of capital and the temporal volatility of the latter in the study of macroeconomic problems.

Austrian school briefly

Austrian School Economists adhere to methodological individualism, which they describe as the analysis of human activity from the point of view of individuals. Representatives of the Austrian school argue that the only way to build a meaningful economic theory- logically derive it from the basic principles of human activity, calling such a method praxeological. In addition, although field experiments are often used by followers of the economic mainstream, " Austrians' indicate that experimental verification of economic models is nearly impossible, since the normal economic activity of people - the subject of economic research - cannot be reproduced under artificial conditions.

Austrian School of Economics definitely refers to the neoclassical bourgeois current of economic knowledge, which appeared due to the marginalist revolution of the 1970s associated with the "breakthrough" in the theory of value. That's why Austrian school also known as - Austrian school of marginal utility or Austrian school of marginalism. It was marginalism that laid new foundations Western economic theory, on which it has been developing ever since. Although Austrian school separates itself from the mainstream of Western economic knowledge, but stands on all the same foundations, the main of which is the assumption taken as an axiom that economic entities possess "reasonableness", by which self-interest is meant. As if every person has knowledge of the subjective value of each thing and starts any exchange or even production, only because of the desire to get the maximum benefit. , like all neoclassical economic thought, reduce all economic relations to exchange.

It's obvious that Austrian School of Economics and all neoclassical economics the question of the finitude of capitalism and the class struggle were left out of the scope of the study, which provided them with support from the capitalist countries.

Actually, the Western mainstream of economic knowledge considered and continues to consider today - the Austrian school for the blurring of the scientific foundations of marginalism and the denial of the use of the mathematical apparatus in analysis - side course, especially since its isolation is due to some of its provisions, which bring it closer to Marxism. Keynesianism as a new wave of enthusiasm in Western neoclassical economic thought in the 30s of the 20th century threw the Austrian school to the periphery for several decades. Only a cooling towards Keynesianism in the late 70s allowed the Austrian school to reassert itself, as interest in the theory and practice of the counter grew. Neo classical theory The market again drew attention to abstract models based more on the psychology of individual behavior, where the Austrian school already had significant developments.

The main representatives of the Austrian school

  • ] first generation - Carl Menger (1840−1921) ( founder of the Austrian school), Theodor Herzka (1845-1924), and others.
  • second generation - Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk (1851−1914), Friedrich von Wieser (1851−1926), Eugen von Philippovich von Philippsberg (1858−1917), Emil Sachs (1845−1927);
  • third generation - Ludwig von Mises (1881-1973), Karl Schlesinger (1889-1938), H. Mayer (1879-1955), Richard von Strigl (1891-1942), Leo Illy (nee Senfeld) (1888-1952) , Benjamin Anderson (1886-1949), Frank Fetter (1863-1949);
  • fourth generation - Friedrich von Hayek (1899-1992), Oskar Morgenstern (1902-1977), Fritz Machlup (1902-1983), Paul Rosenstein-Rodan (1902-1985), Gottfried von Haberler (1900-1995), Henry Hazlitt ( 1894-1993), Friedrich Lutz (1901-1975), Felix Kaufmann (1895-1949);
  • fifth generation - Murray Rothbard (1926-1995), Israel Kirzner (b. 1930), Ludwig Lachmann (1906-1990), George Shackle (G.L.S. Shackle) (1903-1992);
  • sixth generation - Hans-Hermann Hoppe (born 1949), Jörg Guido Hulsman (born 1966), Jesus Huerta de Soto (born 1956), Peter Boettke (born 1960), Chris Coyne, Steven Horwitz (Steven Horwitz, b. 1964), Peter Leeson (Peter T. Leeson), Frederic Saute (Frederic Sautet), Roger Garrison (b. 1944) and others.

To some extent related in their views, but not fully related to the scientists of the Austrian school, are also well-known economists Joseph Schumpeter (1883-1950), John Bates Clark (1847-1938) and Max Otte (born 1964).

School representatives in the CIS

In the Russian Empire, Orzhentsky Roman Mikhailovich can be noted.

In Russian federation:

  • Boris Lvin
  • Viktor Agroskin
  • Yuri Antonovich
  • Valery Kizilov
  • Alexander Kuryaev
  • Anatoly Levenchuk
  • Vadim Novikov
  • Grigory Sapov
  • Pavel Valerievich Usanov.

In Belarus - Alexander Kovalev, Yaroslav Romanchuk.

History of the development of the Austrian school

Austrian school takes its name from the origins of its founders and early adopters, including Karl Menger, Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk, and Ludwig von Mises. Notable Austrian economists of the 20th century also include Henry Hazlitt, Murray Rothbard, and Nobel laureate Friedrich von Hayek.

Austrian school of marginal utility

At the end of the 19th century, Karl Marx became the undisputed authority among economists. However, the success of Karl Marx led not only to the emergence of a wave of imitators, but also to the emergence of numerous critical theories, the authors of which, in the first place, were not satisfied with the theory of class struggle, which followed from the principle of capitalism discovered by Marx - in the form of capitalist appropriation of surplus value. It was necessary to disengage from Marx at the level of philosophical foundations, therefore, at the end of the 19th century, in parallel with the establishment of Marxism, there was a revolution of marginalists who developed a theory of value based on the rarity and usefulness of consumer goods in the sphere of exchange for an individual. Marginalists reduced all economic relations to the exchange of things, in which each individual pursues the maximum benefit - the maximum satisfaction of his needs.

To give such an approach to the concept of cost the appearance of "scientific" - the majinalists had to "drag" into such as "the subjective attitude of an individual to a thing" (attributing to people from birth knowledge about the degree of usefulness of all goods), which in fact was a complete absurdity, but marginalists, through the invented concept of rationality, managed to form a completely logical theory of marginal utility. Representatives of the Austrian school of marginalism suggested the existence of objective rationality in the behavior of people, as if inherent in the entire human race in the sense - greed is a natural trait of any person. They accepted as an axiom the assumption that each person exchanges things, driven by a subjective desire for profitability, and even pursue this profitability as a goal in the organization of production. Since subjectivism correlates poorly with reality, economic relations are considered in abstract models with not very defined boundaries. At the same time, the "Austrians" have one answer to criticism about the artificiality of their models - in reality, everything is distorted by influence.

Today, marginalists en masse have entered neoclassical economics, which is a vague cloud of concepts under the general name (Economics) - a mix of countless inferences based on statistics.

Economics or otherwise - neoclassical, as the main stream of Western economic knowledge - is a set of private concepts based on statistics, more often at the level economics of a separate enterprise. The goal of economics is to study individual behavior in the process of acquiring goods and developing recommendations for efficient business conduct. An innumerable number of diverse articles have been written on the problems of microeconomics in neoclassicism.

But macroeconomics contains completely contradictory concepts. The question of the “finiteness of capitalism” is not raised at all in neoclassicism, and the phrase “collapse of capitalism” is generally banned in economics.

Austrian school theory

At the beginning of the 20th century, as a result of the next Keynesian revolution in Western economics representatives of the Austrian school of marginalism were relegated to the background for several decades. However, in the early 1970s, during the weakening of Keynesianism, interest in micro economic analysis of the behavior and preferences of an individual buyer when buying goods, which pulled the Austrian school out of oblivion, since all economic problems are considered and solved by the "Austrian" at the micro level - the enterprise and the individual.

The well-forgotten methodological individualism of the Austrian school, based on the exaggeration of the importance of the knowledge of an individual as a participant in the exchange, suddenly became in demand in Western economic science. That's why Austrian school resurfaced as a separate movement, and its representatives were retroactively awarded the Nobel Prize.

Another difference between the Austrian school and the economic mainstream is denial of the mathematical apparatus what was once thought a sign of backwardness this direction, and today allows it to maintain integrity and cover a wider range of phenomena, especially in microeconomics. Another dignity of the Austrian school is the creation within its framework of a consistent through the history of all mankind.

Oleg Grigoriev and the Austrian school

He was familiar with the Austrian school, since he worked in the USSR State Planning Committee. At that time, state planning theorists only declared their commitment to Marxist political economy, while on practice Soviet planners were guided the provisions of just the Austrian school. Initially, he considered his theory, called a word in the bosom of neoclassical economic theory, which in Russia replaced political economy. But it turned out that neoconomics is a completely separate science. His is a research program whose purpose is to study the history of the economy that led mankind to the current economic crisis.

At the same time, it is built as a historical theory open to refutation, for which the main provisions of Marxist political economy and neoclassical economic theory are specially considered. Austrian school of marginalism still cannot claim to be a full-fledged economic theory, although due to the breadth of its postulates like marxism managed to explain the cross-cutting history of mankind.

We need to understand the reason why Austrian school continues to be popular - especially among the townsfolk, and with the lowering of the level of scientists to the same level (it's just that the crisis showed all the inconsistency of the entire orthodox economics). The fact is that austrian school - normative theory- she represents theory about HOW IT SHOULD BE, therefore, it is always in an advantageous "position of criticism" - and other theories and actions of real economic authorities. herself Austrian school does not have any positive real proposals for a way out of the crisis, but representatives of the Austrian school how scientific populists are always ready to declare - what they know " HOW TO". Fortunately, no one has been using the services of the Austrian school for a long time, but it has already become customary that representatives of the Austrian school constantly make vociferous statements (usually in hindsight) about their supposedly come true predictions. Most of the economic sensations and predictions (for example, about the return of gold to the place of money) are just "stuffing" from scientists from the Austrian school.

see also

  • Avtonomov V. S. The Austrian school and its representatives // Economic Literature. (Russian) - 24.08.2009.
  • Klein P. Introduction // Hayek F. The fate of liberalism in the XX century. - M.: IRISEN, Thought; Chelyabinsk: Sotsium, 2009. - P. 11. This collection is a translation of the IV volume from the Collected Works of Hayek "The Fortunes of Liberalism: Essays on Austrian Economics and the Ideal of Freedom" (edited by Peter G. Klein. - Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1992. - 287 p.).
  • Hayek F. Joseph Schumpeter (1883−1950) // Hayek F. op.cit., p. 195. A little later, F. Hayek indicates that the first [German-language] book was written in the Mengerian tradition, but the views of J. Schumpeter subsequently changed dramatically (“were discarded”) and the book was never translated into English.
  • Hayek F. John Bates Clark (1847−1938) // Hayek F. Op. cit., p. 51.
  • Boris Lvin - Moscow Libertarium
  • Boris Levin's blog
  • Viktor Agroskin - Moscow Libertarium
  • Viktor Agroskin's blog
  • Antonovich Yuri Nikolaevich. Southern Federal University, Department of Innovative and International Management.
  • Valeriy Kizilov: National Research University Higher School of Economics
  • Blog Valery Kizilov
  • Yuri Kuznetsov
  • Yury Kuznetsov's blog
  • Kuryaev Alexander Viktorovich. Editor-in-chief of the Sotsium publishing house
  • Blog of Alexander Kuryaev
  • Levenchuk Anatoly - Moscow Libertarium
  • Blog of Anatoly Levenchuk
  • Novikov Vadim Vitalievich - Institute of Economic Policy. E. T. Gaidara
  • Blog of Vadim Novikov
  • Bureau of Grigory Sapov
  • Grigory Sapov's blog
  • Usanov Pavel Valerievich - Higher School of Economics - St. Petersburg
  • SpringerLink - The Review of Austrian Economics
  • Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics
  • Prague Conference on Political Economy
  • Bukharin N. I. Foreword // Political Economy of Rentier. - Orbita, 1988. - 192
  • Literature

    • The main works of representatives of the school[edit | edit wiki text]
    • K. Menger. Foundations of political economy. In the book: The Austrian School in Political Economy: K. Menger, E. Böhm-Bawerk, F. Wieser: Per. with him. / Foreword, comments, comp. V. S. Avtonomov. - M.: Economics, 1992. - (Economic heritage.) - ISBN 5-282-01471-8.
    • Vizer F. Theory of social economy (selected ch.) - In the book: The Austrian School in Political Economy: K. Menger, E. Böhm-Bawerk, F. Vizer: Per. with him. / Foreword, comments, comp. V. S. Avtonomov. - M.: Economics, 1992. - (Economic heritage.) - ISBN 5-282-01471-8.
    • Mises L. Liberalism in the classical tradition. − M.: Sotsium; Economics, 2001. - 239 p.
    • Mises L. Socialism. − M.: "Catallaxy", 1994.
    • Mises L. Theory and History: An Interpretation of Socio-Economic Evolution. - M.: UNITI-DANA, 2001. - 295 p.
    • Mises L. Human activity: Treatise on economic theory / 2nd rev. ed. - Chelyabinsk: Sotsium, 2005. - 878 s - ISBN 5-901901-29-0.
    • Hayek F. Individualism and economic order. - M.: Izograph, 2000. - 256 p.

    Works about the Austrian school

    • Austrian school / Alter L. B. // A - Engob. - M .: Soviet Encyclopedia, 1969. - (Great Soviet Encyclopedia: [in 30 volumes] / editor-in-chief A. M. Prokhorov; 1969-1978, vol. 1).
    • Avtonomov V.S. The Austrian school and its representatives. − In the book: The Austrian School in Political Economy: K. Menger, E. Böhm-Bawerk, F. Wieser: Per. with him. / Foreword, comments, comp. V. S. Avtonomov. - M.: Economics, 1992. - (Economic heritage.) - ISBN 5-282-01471-8.
    • Antonovich Yu.N. Austrian theory of capital and capital goods // Post-crisis world: globalization, multipolarity, modernization, institutions: materials of the International Scientific and Practical Conference (Rostov-on-Don, May 20-22, 2010): in 3 volumes. V.1 / under ed. A. Yu. Arkhipova, Yu. M. Osipova, V. A. Aleshina, V. N. Ovchinnikova. - ISBN 978-5-9502-0573-6.
    • Blaug M. Austrian theory of capital and interest // Economic thought in retrospect = Economic Theory in Retrospect. - M.: Delo, 1994. - S. 461-526. - XVII, 627 p. - ISBN 5-86461-151-4.
    • Blyumin I. G. Austrian school // Criticism of bourgeois political economy: In 3 volumes. - M.: Publishing house of the Academy of Sciences of the USSR, 1962. - T. I. Subjective school in bourgeois political economy. - S. 70-151. - VIII, 872 p. - 3,200 copies.
    • Bukharin N. The Political Economy of Rentier: The Theory of Value and Profit of the Austrian School
    • Gene Callahan Economics for ordinary people: Fundamentals of the Austrian School of Economics. - Chelyabinsk: Sotsium, 2006.
    • Tugan-Baranovsky M. I. The Austrian School // Essays on the Modern History of Political Economy: (Smith, Malthus, Ricardo, Sismondi, Historical School, Katheder-Socialists, Austrian School, Owen, Saint-Simon, Fourier, Proudhon, Rodbertus, Marx ). - St. Petersburg: Ed. magazine "God's World", 1903. - S. 206-224. - X, 434 p.
    • Huerta de Soto H. Austrian School of Economics: The Market and Entrepreneurial Creativity. - Chelyabinsk: Sotsium, 2007. - 202 s - (Series "Austrian School". Issue 1). − ISBN 978-5-901901-69-4.

Period 60-70 years of the XIX century. considered a turning point in the development of economic science. It was then that at the same time in three schools, which are called Austrian, Lausanne and Cambridge at the place of origin, formed theoretical basis neoclassical approach. His starting point and the basis for the orientation of economic analysis was the subjective theory of value, developed on the basis of the principle of marginal utility.

The Austrian school received the greatest fame and international recognition. Its foundations were laid by Carl Menger (1840-1921), who published his work The Foundations of Political Economy in 1871. His theoretical views were developed in the works of two of his other students and collaborators - Friedrich Wieser (1851-1926) and Eugen Böhm-Bawerk (1851-1914).

Wieser's main works:

  • "The Origin and Main Laws of Economic Value" (1884)
  • "Natural Value" (1889)

The most important works of Böhm-Bawerk:

  • "Fundamentals of the theory of the value of economic goods" (1886)
  • "Capital and interest" (1884-1889)

The views of these scientists are similar and complement each other. Menger developed the foundations of the theory of marginal utility as applied to individual acts of exchange. Wieser, who introduced the term "marginal utility", used this theory to estimate the cost of production costs. Böhm-Bawerk developed further the views of his predecessors, creating a detailed theory of interest. Therefore, we can talk about the unified theory of marginal utility of the Austrian school.

The main feature of the methodology of the Austrian school is a logical-deductive qualitative analysis. It is aimed at studying the behavior of an economic entity in order to reveal through it the cause and essence of all economic phenomena. This is the so-called atomistic method or the Robinsonade method. The other side of the method is subjective psychological analysis, since the psychology of the economic individual in this theory determines all economic goals. Thus, K. Menger considered economic science to be an unfinished branch of psychology.

The Austrian school neglected quantitative analysis, i. did not address the issues of commensuration and comparison of utility. She used verbal presentation, which at that time made her popular in comparison with the works of W. Jevons and L. Walras.

The main feature of the approach proposed by the Austrian school is the following: the reduction of value to the costs of labor, land and capital is unacceptable. The cost (value) is determined by the degree of useful effect of a certain good. At the same time, the objective value (market prices) that exists independently of human consciousness and the subjective value differed. Subjective value shows how much a given person values ​​this or that thing in terms of his well-being. The value of a thing, Böhm-Bawerk argues, is measured by its marginal utility, i.e. value is determined not by the utility of each commodity, but by the utility of the last unit of a supply of a particular consumer good. Marginal utility depends, therefore, on the supply (rarity) of the good and on the intensity of the need for it. The higher the intensity of need for a given supply of goods, the higher the marginal utility for the individual. Conversely, the greater the supply of a good at a given intensity, the lower the marginal utility.

Böhm-Bawerk identifies three basic rules that participants in the process of social exchange should use:

  • firstly, the exchange must be beneficial (i.e., the good received in exchange is of greater utility than the good given)
  • secondly, everyone strives to make a deal with a greater benefit for themselves
  • thirdly, it is better to make a deal with less profit than to refuse to exchange at all

The Austrians present this problem as follows. The market is the point where the interests (assessments) of sellers and buyers collide. (Recall that this stage of abstraction does not imply the presence of production, and none of the participants in the exchange compares the price offered to him with the cost of labor). Each of them has its own assessment of the goods sold. So the buyer of a horse proceeds from how much he needs the horse and what is its usefulness, and the seller from what damage to his economy the sale of the horse will bring. In other words, according to this theory, each participant in the exchange - the buyer and the seller - has already developed subjective assessments in advance. The Austrian school considers the market price as the resultant of the subjective assessments of sellers and buyers.

Suppose there is one buyer and one seller. The buyer values ​​the horse at 100 monetary units, and the seller - in 80. Böhm-Bawerk proves that the subjective assessment of the seller is the lower one. Prices are set within these boundaries. In the case of bilateral competition between sellers and buyers, the boundaries of price setting are determined by the super-subjective assessment of the last of the buyers who entered into the transaction and the subjective assessment of the strongest of the sellers eliminated from the market, and from below - by the subjective assessment of the last of the sellers who entered into the transaction and the subjective assessment of the strongest of the sellers eliminated from the market. buyers market. Since there are other buyers and sellers on the market, competition arises that “pushes” the price up and down, and if there are a significant number of participants in the exchange, the price will be within narrower boundaries than in an isolated exchange.

As a result, individual marginal utilities determine how much of good B its owners will offer in exchange for good A, and vice versa. As a result of the exchange, individual marginal utilities are spontaneously transformed in the market into the social marginal utility of goods B and A. This utility is measured by the price at which supply and demand mutually cover each other. By setting the public estimate of the marginal utility of a commodity at the level of the individual estimate of the "marginal buyer", all other buyers (whose estimates are higher) receive a tangible benefit. The same benefit is received by each buyer (except for the "marginal") if he purchases at the same market price several units of a product whose marginal utility for him decreases.

Some attention in the concept of the Austrian school is given to the evaluation of production goods. Their value (cost) is derived from the marginal utility of consumer goods. Thus, according to Böhm-Bawerk, it is not the cost of flour that determines the cost of bread, but, on the contrary, the cost of bread determines the cost of flour, which, in turn, determines the cost of wheat, rye, etc., i.e. production costs derive value from their products. The value of the factors involved in production is thus of a derivative, “imputed” nature.

Böhm-Bawerk's theory of interest can be considered the most original of the developments of the Austrian school. For example, imagine that the lender presents the borrower for one year cash in the amount of 1000 monetary units. Since the owner of money assumes a decrease in his estimates of marginal utility, receiving the same amount of 1000 monetary units from the debtor would lead to a decrease in his welfare. Therefore, the creditor, obeying the principle of rational behavior, does not intend to put up with such a prospect, and demands the return of not 1000 monetary units, but 1100. Thus, he compensates for the possible deterioration of his well-being in the coming year. The resulting difference (100) is regarded by Böhm-Bawerk as a percentage, and the exchange is represented as equivalent.

This theory is based on the original principle of the Austrian school, which boils down to the fact that objects of the present time are valued more than future goods. On its basis, the psychological law of underestimation of future benefits was established. The very formulation of the question of the role of the time factor in the evaluation of goods is also important. In the future, this idea received a deep development.

The ideas of the Austrian school had a serious impact on the methodology of economic science. This applies, first of all, to the subjective approach developed within the framework of the philosophical and ethical concept. It was the "human factor", the individual with his desire for the most complete satisfaction of needs, that was the starting point for the Austrian school.

The theory of marginal utility became the basis of the modern theory of consumer choice, made it possible to identify the motivation for the microeconomic behavior of individuals. It predetermined the approach not only to solving the problem of individual utility, but also the assessment of social utility and preferences.

Today, the Austrian School of Economics is in the backyard of economic academic thought. On the margins in the sense that representatives of the economic academic mainstream try to keep any original scientific trends and concepts out of the educational process. But the school itself does not become less interesting from this and has a large number of adherents around the world. Unfortunately, the school is partly discredited in the eyes of people of statist convictions. Such discrediting occurred for the reason that among the supporters of the Austrian school there are many representatives of the libertarian movement, who believe that a person should be left to himself, who cannot withstand competition in the market, has no right to count on the support of society. But it is quite clear that no politician (even very liberal convictions) can accept such a savage approach as a basis. First, it is politically unsafe. Secondly, everyone understands that not every person in a particular period of time can find himself in the market. For one reason or another, many of us sometimes need social support. In the economy, there are no only successful and wealthy people.

But what did the representatives of the Austrian school write, what conclusions did they come to, were they all as one supporters of complete non-intervention of the state in the economy? Few people know, but one of the founders of the Austrian school of economics, Baron Friedrich von Wieser (1851-1926) "tried to justify the need for state intervention and central planning ( he again used the term "planning" for the first time in Western economic theory - Ya.S.) in order to translate the principles of marginal utility into practice and ensure the optimal functioning of the economy."

True, for this, many modern Austrians are trying to attribute Wieser's legacy to the German historical school. But this is unlikely to be done, since it was Wieser who "wrote the first systematic treatise-textbook of the Austrian school -" The Theory of Social Economy "(1914). Wieser's contribution to Austrian theory is very peculiar ... he became famous for giving bright names and memorable formulations of many ideas of marginalism.It was he who first used the terms "marginal utility" (Grenznutzen), "imputation" (Zurechnung), "Gossen's laws".

Many modern Austrians are also trying to disown Joseph Schumpeter, arguing that he has gone too far from the ideals of the Austrian school. The main reproach against him is as follows: "Schumpeter's originality and independence, his desire and ability to go against the current manifested themselves in other moments. As you know, the Austrian school fundamentally rejected the use of mathematics in economic analysis. But, while studying at the University of Vienna, Schumpeter independently (without listening to a single special lecture) studied mathematics and the works of economists and mathematicians from O. Cournot to K. Wicksell so much that in the year of defending his dissertation for the title of Doctor of Law (1906) he published a profound article " On the Mathematical Method in Theoretical Economics", in which, to the great displeasure of his teachers, he concluded that mathematical economics is promising, on which the future of economic science will be based. Love for mathematics remained for life: Schumpeter considered lost every day when he did not read books on mathematics and ancient Greek authors. "At the same time, Schumpeter was not at all a mathematician author. already repulsed.

According to libertarians, the use of mathematics in economics contributes to the formation of an unfree, regulated economic system, in which politicians get the opportunity to use various formulas to control society. At the same time, it is completely ignored that mathematics entered the economy firmly at the moment when economic life itself began to become more complicated, it became difficult to get by with speculative reasoning alone. For this reason, many economists began to come to the conclusion that the role of mathematics will grow.

Schumpeter also made a significant contribution to debunking the myth of monopolies: "From Schumpeter's reasoning about the role of large corporations, the special significance of monopolies as subjects of innovative activity, many of his followers deduced

position on the relationship between market structure, the presence of monopolies and the level of innovation, which is often called the "Schumpeter hypothesis": "the monopoly position of the firm is a key condition for successful innovation."

Indeed, Schumpeter proves that a monopoly is by no means always a pure economic evil. On the contrary, in terms of dynamic efficiency, creating conditions for major innovations, a large monopoly business has great advantages over a company operating in conditions of perfect competition.

At the same time, he emphasizes that in the trend it is innovation that destroys monopolies: "... the impact of innovations, for example, new technologies, on existing industry structures in the long term prevents the strategy of limiting production, maintaining dominant positions to maximize profits." The economic history of innovation, patterns of emergence and change of industries - the leaders of technological progress show that each new product that forms the industry, as a rule, is associated with the activities of one or another large corporation. Automobiles are Ford, nylon is DuPont, semiconductors are Bell, computers are IBM, software is Microsoft, processors are Intel, and they form a far from complete series of examples from the history of the 20th century.

Today in Russia they often talk about the dominance of monopolies in the economy, which reduces its efficiency as a whole. They propose to do something with Gazprom, Russian Railways, Rosneft, etc. But at the same time, they do not take into account that when the time comes, these monopoly structures will change themselves. Even if they are controlled by the state.

Not a single structure can be constant in time, not change its appearance, not lose its position in the market. Joseph Schumpeter showed the nature of monopolies very well. This is a completely objective market phenomenon. Very often, monopolies are much more effective in implementing the so-called. "complementary" innovations than do disparate market agents.

I wonder if any private passenger railway company (one of many) could implement the Sapsan project? Frankly, there are big doubts about this. But the organization of high-speed traffic in Russia is the very "complementary" innovation in the field of organizing passenger transportation in Russia. And, despite all the criticism that fell on Russian Railways in connection with the acquisition and launch of Sapsan, the project took place and turned out to be profitable.

The railroad in this case acts as one of the most illustrative examples. But we can recall the gas pipe, for access to which there is an active struggle.

Supporters of reform in the gas industry cannot give a comprehensive answer to the question of who will be responsible for managing such a complex facility as the gas transmission system, from whose pocket will it be paid for its maintenance, what financial burden will certain companies bear? And the financial burden in the event of "demonopolization" of the pipe should increase significantly, since access to it by independent gas producers will be significantly simplified. This means that capacities will operate at a higher load, which will require large financial injections to maintain the system.

With all the questions to Gazprom, the efficiency of its work, which are objectively fair, the solution of such problems must be approached with great caution. And even if "a thorough check of the" Schumpeter's hypothesis "on the statistical materials of a large number of industries and markets (American statistics, for example, regularly publish indicators of the share of production for the four largest companies in the industry) did not unequivocally confirm or refute the high efficiency of innovation in large monopoly corporations," In practice, we can still see that many issues can only be solved by large companies.

It would seem that there are specific practical issues. And what about the Austrian school? But if you delve into many aspects of theory, you can see their close relationship with practice, our daily life. If we discard the ideological component, identify the most useful and interesting in a particular school, then it will be much easier to explain what is happening in the economy.

Of course, the Austrian school is not limited to Wieser and Schumpeter. But it was on them that I wanted to focus attention, since they make a huge contribution to the development of economic science in general and the Austrian school in particular. But they are the ones least often referred to by libertarians. On Ludwig von Mises all the time. But not on Wieser and Schumpeter. The latter is generally denied the right to be considered an Austrian economist. But they are interesting because they made a huge contribution to science, while being remembered for their originality and dissimilarity to others.

    When determining the characteristic of Utility and Good, Menger receives two items in one shell. It seems to me more familiar and corresponding to the meaning of the perception of these words is their meaning:
    Benefit - an object or relation - a carrier of utility as a property to satisfy a person's need, both directly and through the processes of natural development, social and economic interaction. This shows that not all goods can come into direct and immediate contact with an individual, but at the same time, in their meaning, they act as a blessing.

    The Law of Cause and Effect is usually considered in sequence from cause to effect, and life shows that the effect is the search for the cause. If we take into account that human life itself is created and built from the micro level and that this happens spontaneously to a certain extent, then not everything will look unambiguously certain. The mass of causes can be established only when there is some event, action, result, and the name of the cause becomes a formalized explanation of the effect. She will always be there. If we take any event or state as a Consequence, then everything that preceded it - a lot of conditions, circumstances and states, and so it is proposed, as a Cause, then wouldn't such an approach be too "indiscriminate"?
    The very process of interaction with the good or its use allows you to discover and accept its usefulness. Not the simultaneous occurrence of the conditions listed by Menger allows the object to act as a blessing, but the process of its use causes the emergence of accompanying meanings and circumstances.

    About the time.
    Time is a process of transformation, and the perception of this process acts as a sense of time. In Menger, the opposite is true: "Each process of transformation consists of emergence and development and is conceivable only in time."

    If we take into account the nature of the establishment of the relationship between persons and goods, then we can expand the above classification by introducing definitions of captured (power and organizational types) and law-produced goods.

    I believe that it is completely meaningless to link the value of goods with their quantity available for disposal. And it can also be said that there are no goods that could be obtained without labor. Of course, for some time it can be assumed that these include air, sometimes warm, like habitat and sunlight. It is possible to argue about the basic conditions for the existence of life and to assert that these benefits are not valuable, unless one takes into account the will and work of the creator of this world. These are the products of "another economy", to the level of understanding of which our consciousness has not risen. But air has already turned into a natural material, the consumption of which has already begun to be deliberately limited, since the limit of use is already visible. It is better not to talk about water and fruits in the same sense. This is one argument for decoupling the question of the relationship between the value of goods and their scarcity.

    In order to better understand this issue, it is necessary, initially, to proceed from the conditions and circumstances of the preservation and reproduction (extended in qualitative and qualitative terms) of life, a separate life, because value acts as a subjective relation and an incommensurable value for different people. Value is a manifestation of an individual attitude to a particular good in their overall structure. It has no direct connection with the need and its satisfaction, as well as with use and exchange value, price and value. Value is manifested only in the formed structure of consumption. Many newly emerging goods have a high value compared to others in the overall structure of goods, they often become the subject of imaginative and psychologically enhanced demand, but they do not have a corresponding value proportional to the cost.

    A high concentration of a certain good in an individual is for him the basis of trade interaction with other persons and obtaining material rights. In fact, any excess of the quantity of goods over the immediate physical need always turns into material rights (sometimes even into the loss of them). Apparently, at first, there was a spontaneous deviation, and then its place is taken by a specialization in deviation for the production of material rights as an economic type of need.

    Having written the above, I did not at all expect to find such a definition in Menger:
    "Utility is the suitability of an object to serve the satisfaction of human needs, and therefore (precisely as known utility) is general condition the nature of the benefits. And non-economic goods are useful to the same extent as economic ones, due to their ability to satisfy human needs, and this suitability of them must also be known by people, since otherwise they could not become goods at all.
    I can't help but agree with this definition.

    Menger is looking for stable relationships between value and cost, but these are categories of a completely different plan: value is a more psychological category, cost is an economic one. There is only one connection here - everything, one way or another, closes on the subject of these relations. He tries to deduce and show the relationship between value and price, but these are just similar words, besides, the latter is an economic declaration.

    Initially, economic exchange was based on the deviation of the actual availability of goods from physical need and the transformation of this deviation into material rights, followed by specialization in this deviation. In the future, the life of the subjects economic relations was planned and implemented on the basis of the intention of obtaining material rights on the basis of specialization in deviation.

    We must not lose sight of the fact that the basis of economic interaction is not just an exchange, but a set of acts of purchase and sale, presented separately on the market. Always in each of these acts, on the one hand, material rights appear.

    Using the category "Utility" to find reasons for economic interaction does not seem to me to make any sense. It's subjective economic characteristic. Value and utility are manifested in economic interaction not directly, but as figurative foundations of demand and as one of the engines of socio-economic progress.

    Price is just a declaration of value. It is rather difficult to deduce economic laws from declarations. For some designation of the procedure and environment for setting prices, one could start from several influencing circumstances:
    1 - Prices are set and exist only in the economic environment;
    2 - Prices are set by the subjects of relations;
    3 - Comprehension of the position of the subject in relation to setting the price is carried out by a person .. (Example of this chapter)
    4 -Setting a price is one of the manifestations of economic freedom;
    5 - Setting a price acts as an intention to create value.

    >Menger is looking for stable relationships between value and cost, but
    > these are categories of a completely different plan: value is more
    ironically, the terms "value" and
    "cost" came into Russian as translations
    the same English word - value
    When translating "Capital" into Russian, value was intentionally and for ideological reasons translated as "cost", because "cost" in Russian has a somewhat more objectivist coloration. Thus, the objective nature of value was emphasized, which is in full agreement with the labor theory of value, with which Marx's materialism is consistent.
    If you don't take my word for it, refer to any classic English text on the theory of value. You will not find a distinction (at least at the level of designation in different words) of value and cost. Only the word value is used. Even in "Capital".

    As a matter of fact, I will not object to the remark. I will only note that no matter how the terms "value" and "cost" are related to each other for an economic good, none of these characteristics is given objectively, i.e. regardless of the evaluator.
    Many authors have already criticized the objective (including labor) theory of value and have come to a subjective theory. The latest (and one of the best) exposition you will find in Mises in "Human Action".

    >Price is just a declaration of value.
    Prices are ratios of values ​​of economic goods, expressed in money, according to which really there is an exchange of these goods. Whether they are declarative or not (I don't understand what this means) - the exchange is going on, which means that prices determine the conditions of human activity. And then, whether we like it or not, we are obliged to determine the patterns of exchange, taking into account prices.

    >Setting a price acts as an intention to create value.
    Senseless nonsense.

    >material rights
    And I, naive, for some reason have always been convinced that rights are intangible by definition ...

    >is not just an exchange, but a set of acts
    >buying and selling, presented on the market separately
    ...which economists call exchange in the general sense of the word
    The expression "an exchange takes place in the market" means that a certain number of "acts of purchase and sale, presented separately on the market," take place.

    In the market there is not an exchange, but an exchange. Superobjection by God!

    In Menger, indeed, the relationship between the utility of a good and the good itself is rather vaguely defined. Therefore, misunderstandings are possible here.

    I would advise you to start studying the foundations of subjectivist theory from a different interpretation - from Mises' work "Human Activity" - there is basically the same thing, but there is much less room for confusion in the head. And judging by your subsequent comments, there is confusion and quite serious.

    Incidentally, in expounding the doctrine of the economic good, Mises does not refer to the term "utility" at all.

    I do not see any basis for presenting value as use and exchange value, as well as the transition from these phrases to the concept of price. I think that, in this case, in fact, the development of concepts is not from value to price, but a rather unconvincing justification adapts to the latter. Such a justification is similar to a systemic delusion, the use of which distorts the structure of economic interaction.


    A commodity is a (material) carrier of value intended for sale.
    It can be said that the starting point in the appearance and existence of a product is the intention to obtain material rights in monetary form as a result of the sale of an existing or manufactured product. And not vice versa, as often seems to be the case.

    I really like the trick with the substitution of the history of money for the history of the monetary device, which for some reason is usually called money circulation. The entire history of money consists of the facts of their creation (production) and use. Money always has a complete cycle: production - use. Therefore, it is possible to speak of money circulation only as a non-existent phenomenon .. But on the other hand, something can always be said about the circulation of money carriers - about their transfer from account to account or from pocket to pocket along with the emergence and use of money. What passes for history monetary circulation, obviously, is the history of the monetary device.

    I think that such a widespread fairy tale "about a white bull" is not able to explain the nature of the origin of money. "Bull" gave value to the bearer of money, not to money. When moving, "Bull" could gain weight and lose weight. And it does not matter at all whether he acted in this case either in the role of cattle, or in the role of precious metal. Not a single commodity, regardless of its value, has ever been money, but, of course, some of them were carriers of money.

    Yes, you are driving yourself into a terrible jungle. And metaphysicians never dreamed of separating the concepts from themselves "money was never money", congratulations.
    I'm stupid to understand this, to return from a simple Spinoza.

    Sergey, hello!
    Personally, you can write off everything that has been said to my eccentricity, but, in the meantime, pay attention to the fact that we are talking in the margins of a work called "The Foundations of Political Economy." In addition, it is presented as the basis of political economy. To me, these foundations appear as a parachute of political economy, which began to take shape in flight. It is no longer possible to ignore this. I must also say that I attach due importance to this work and the role of the author in highlighting the issue.
    Actually, what did I say? It may be that a certain slate in political economy is clean again.

    Speaking of Ludwig von Mises, here are his words:
    "The struggle for freedom, in the final analysis, is not resistance to despots or oligarchs, but resistance to the despotism of public opinion. It is not a struggle of many against a few, but a struggle of a minority - sometimes a minority consisting of one person - against the majority"

    "The dissenting minority is undemocratic because it refuses to accept the opinion of the majority as truth. All means of "liquidating" these rebellious scoundrels are "democratic" and therefore moral"

    The words are simple, but the idea is wonderful. It's Mises! ("Theory and History")

    Start
    70s of the XIX century. in the history of the world
    economic thought was marked as
    called the marginalist revolution. IN
    there is a large proportion of such dating
    conventions; for example, the basics
    marginal utility theories
    formulated by G. G. Gossen for a long time
    the forgotten work of 1844, and the beginning
    massive penetration
    marginalist ideas into the economic
    literature should only be
    mid 1880s. It went differently
    marginalist revolution in different countries.
    But the fact remains: publications in 1871.
    "Theories of Political Economy" W. St.
    Jevons and "Foundations of political
    economy" by K. Menger, and in 1874 "Elements
    pure political economy" L.
    Walras laid new foundations for Western
    economic theory, on which she has since
    time and develops. Relevance
    offered to the reader of the book is,
    therefore, in that for the first time [neither
    one of the founders
    marginalism (L. Walras, W. St. Jevons, K.
    Menger) was not published in the USSR. From works
    published in this collection were published
    only "Fundamentals of the theory of value
    economic benefits "E. Böhm-Bawerk (1929)]
    given the opportunity to get to know
    one of the origins of modern Western
    economic thought - the Austrian school
    political economy.

    IN
    in this introductory article, we
    Let's try to look at the characteristics
    distinguishing the Austrian school as a whole from
    other areas of marginalism:
    Lausanne school (L. Walras, V. Pareto),
    works of W. St. Jevons and A. Marshall, as well as
    give an individual description
    to each of its three founders,
    presented by their work in this
    book. But first, it must be said
    a few words about the marginalist revolution
    generally. That three people (Jevons,
    Menger and Walras), working independently each
    from each other and relying on completely different
    national scientific traditions, - and in the XIX century.
    national features of English,
    German and French political
    savings were very bright [Blyumin I. G.
    Subjective school in political economy.
    T. I. M .: Publishing house Kom. Academy, 1931], - came to
    very close conclusions, could not be
    random coincidence. Revolution like us
    we know that a revolutionary situation gives rise.
    What was the pre-marginalist
    situation in Western economic theory, and
    more precisely in the theory of value (value), times
    did the revolution take place here?

    dominating
    in this area, the paradigm was based on
    achievements of the English classical school in
    interpretations of J. S. Mill, who in 1848
    inadvertently stated that "fortunately, in
    laws of value there is nothing left
    to find out modern or any
    future author; theory of the subject
    is complete" [Mill J.S. Fundamentals
    political economy. T. 2. M.: Progress, 1986.
    S. 172].

    These
    immutable "laws of value"
    boiled down to the following:

    1. value of a thing
      There is temporary (market) and permanent (natural).
      The latter is the center around
      which he vacillates and strives for
      first;
    2. market value is determined by demand and
      offer. At the same time, demand in turn
      depends on the market value;
    3. natural value in different ways
      determined for non-reproducible and
      freely reproduced goods. In the first
      case (this also includes monopoly
      situations) it depends on the rarity of the thing, in
      second (predominant) - on the amount of costs
      production of goods and their delivery to the market;
    4. production costs are made up of
      wages and return on capital and
      ultimately determined by the number
      labor expended [Mill J.S., Decree. op. T.
      2. S. 222--224].

    So
    Thus, in the classical model, the average
    price level (natural value)
    determined in the field of production and
    set by costs. The offer of the same product
    is determined by the demand that develops at
    given price.

    Takova
    objective production theory
    value in its most concise form. Should
    note that on the European continent this
    theory existed in a slightly different form.
    On the one hand, there was a strong tradition
    ascending to Galiani and Condillac and
    relating the value of a thing to its usefulness.
    On the other hand, the German economic
    literature influenced by powerful
    German philosophy of that time, gave
    much attention to the meaning of the word "value"
    (Wert), correlated it with other human
    values, etc. However, the theory of value on
    continent usually included those described by J.
    S. Mill "laws", although this is how
    rule led to contradictions [Example
    can serve as the famous "Textbook
    political economy" A. Wagner (Wagner A.,
    Nasse A. Lehrbuch der Politischen Okonomie. 2. Aufl. Leipzig, 1875)]. But from
    shortcomings was not free and itself
    classical theory in its Millevian
    option. First, for anyone, even the most
    highly developed and wealthy society (and for
    him in particular) the possibility
    unlimited increase in production
    from which the "theory of costs" originates,
    is the exception rather than the rule.
    Secondly, the objective theory interpreted
    demand for goods as a "black box". That
    little has been said about the determinants
    its factors, came down to the banal
    logical circle: demand affects prices, and
    prices affect demand. Third, dualism
    classical theory of value (completely
    different explanations for free
    reproducible and non-reproducible goods)
    gave no rest to scientists seeking to create
    coherent and comprehensive theory,
    revealing the essence of value (value).
    (Namely, such goals were set before any
    science in those pre-positivist times.) ["We
    we need just such a theory, which all
    phenomena of value would be deduced from one and
    the same beginning, and, moreover, would give them
    exhaustive explanation," Böhm-Bawerk wrote].

    All
    these weaknesses have provoked criticism of the classical
    theories from a variety of perspectives. If
    the German historical school criticized her
    for overly abstract, unhistorical
    character, then K. Marx, on the contrary, resolutely
    cleared the labor cost hypothesis of
    hesitations and reservations that arose from A. Smith,
    D. Ricardo and J. S. Mill, because they
    wanted to reconcile this abstraction with
    the realities of life.

    Third
    the path chosen by the marginalists. They tried
    create a monistic general theory
    values ​​based on presuppositions, completely
    contrary to the premises of the classical
    schools.

    IN
    as the initial elementary phenomenon
    economic life they chose the attitude
    person to thing, manifested in the field
    personal consumption [classical school is not
    included personal consumption in the subject
    political economy, since the influence
    habits, traditions, prejudices and other
    manifestations of irrationality prevails
    here over the impact of competition and
    economic calculation and makes
    human behavior in a given area
    unpredictable. Therefore, in order to
    create a theory of value based on
    relation of man to thing, marginalists
    it took to make this attitude
    rational. Man in the theory of the ultimate
    utility knows the hierarchy of its
    needs and by satisfying them
    to get the most
    welfare]. As K. Menger wrote, "man
    with their needs and their power over
    means of satisfying the latter
    constitutes the starting and ending point
    every human economy" (p. 89).
    From this relationship between needs and
    means of satisfaction, or, speaking
    more familiar language, between usefulness and
    a rarity, marginalists just deduce
    the phenomenon of the value of economic goods.

    Armed
    knowledge of the subjective value of goods,
    economic entities start if they
    it is profitable, exchange or even production.
    Moreover, if for the classical school
    the essence of exchange is to be found in the realm
    production, then for marginalists,
    on the contrary, production itself is
    peculiar indirect view exchange . The purpose of production and exchange for
    each of their members is the best
    satisfying one's needs directly
    or mediated.

    So
    Thus, the marginalists radically
    reframed the cost problem:
    contents of the "black box" (consumer
    estimates and consumer choice) has become
    the main subject of analysis, and causal
    links between production, exchange and
    consumption changed their direction to
    the opposite - the basis of value was not
    past costs, but future utility, etc.

    Of course
    marginalists' alleged motivation
    any economic activity- maximum satisfaction
    individual needs -- looks
    extreme anachronism in the conditions of a developed
    capitalism at the end of the 19th century. However, from our point of view
    view, this premise, taken by itself,
    no more artificial than the postulate
    classical (and Marxist) theory
    the cost of limitless possibilities
    production expansion. How fair
    emphasizes Yu. B. Kochevrin, "the fruitfulness
    abstractions should be defined not in terms of
    the absence of certain realities in it, not according to
    some psychological or
    behavioral assumptions, but from the explanation
    real economic process or its
    essential side" [Kochevrin Yu. B.
    Neoclassical production theory and
    distribution//World economy and
    international relationships. 1987. "10. S. 45].
    The question of the applicability of the classical and
    marginalist abstractions to various
    areas of modern pricing,
    definitely deserves a separate
    conversation and goes beyond this
    introductions.

    Long
    time the Austrian school was considered in
    Western economic literature only as
    one of the driving forces of the marginalist
    a revolution that reached smaller
    success than others, because not
    mastered mathematics. Such
    assessment was formed in the mid-30s of the XX century,
    when different directions of marginalism,
    seemed to be forever merged into a single
    neoclassical current and, moreover, were
    relegated to the background as a result
    the next revolution in economics --
    Keynesian. But in the early 1970s, during
    the weakening of Keynesianism and the revival
    keen interest in microeconomics
    analysis revealed that the Mohicans
    Austrian school L. Mises and F. Hayek (the last
    received the Nobel Prize in 1974) carried
    through all these years, some of the most important
    features of the Austrian school, which did not give it
    merge completely with the neoclassical
    paradigm.

    So
    way, compared with Lausanne and
    Cambridge (Anglo-American) schools
    marginalism, the Austrian school turned out to be
    most clearly defined and durable.
    It is possible with a high degree of certainty
    name famous economists,
    belonging to different generations
    Austrian school, including our
    contemporaries. This is its founder K.
    Menger, his students E. Böhm-Bawerk and F. Wieser (although
    listen to lectures by K. Menger in the Vienna
    they didn’t have a chance to go to university, both of them graduated
    him shortly before the author of The Foundations
    political economy" got there
    professorship), students of E. Böhm-Bawerk
    L. Mises and J. Schumpeter, student of L. Mises F.
    Hayek and his peers G. Haberler, F. Machlup,
    O. Morgenstern (one of the founders of the theory
    games), followers of L. Mises and F. Hayek I.
    Kirzner, L. Lachmann, E. Streisler and others.

    strong
    the influence of various ideas of the Austrian school
    had on the British L. Robbins, J. Hicks and
    J. Shackle, Swede C. Wicksell, Dutchman
    Pearson, Italian M. Pantaleoni,
    Americans R. Ely, S. Patten and others.
    Of course, the Austrian research
    tradition among its various representatives
    manifested itself in various forms and
    degree, but in all cases trace it
    influence is possible.

    What are
    same characteristic features of the Austrian
    schools of political economy? First of all, this
    consistent monistic
    subjectivism: all categories of economic
    science, the Austrians seek to deduce only

    from the relation to the thing of economic
    subject, his preferences, expectations,
    knowledge. How emphatically emphasizes
    Menger, any good in itself, from the point
    economist's point of view, devoid of any
    objective properties, and above all
    values. These properties give them only
    corresponding relation of one or the other
    subject.

    So,
    the essence of interest lies with them in different
    assessment by the subject of present and future benefits,
    production costs - in lost use,
    which is expected to be productive
    good could bring if they were
    used not as it really is, but
    otherwise, etc. At the same time, the subject of the Austrians
    not guaranteed against errors (he may, to
    example, to misjudge one's future
    needs and means of satisfying them)
    and these mistakes of his will not be "discarded"
    market, but will play their part by participating
    along with more correct estimates, in
    determining the price of a given good.

    Special
    the emphasis that the Austrians place on
    future uncertainties and opportunities
    mistakes, the great importance attached to them,
    especially Menger, knowledge of economic
    subject at his disposal
    information, sharply distinguish them from the background
    other marginalists and make their theories
    especially important today, when the problem
    information search and processing is
    front of economic research.

    Can
    boldly assert that the degree
    rationality required of
    business entity located in
    the theories of the Austrians are an order of magnitude lower than in
    Jevons and Walras models. This
    manifests itself, in particular, in
    features of the Austrian school, namely in
    that the Austrians do not use not only
    mathematical research methods, but
    even geometric illustrations of their
    theoretical positions (like Jevons and
    Marshall). This feature of the Austrian school
    catches the eye of everyone who flips through
    this book - you will not find in it not only
    differential equations, but also the usual
    diagrams with supply and demand curves.
    Of course, this can also be explained by the fact that
    founders of the Austrian school,
    educated in law, just
    did not master the technique of mathematics
    analysis [although the same K. Menger, if desired
    could well acquire the necessary skills from
    his brother, an eminent mathematician].
    However, the main reason is completely different.
    The fact is that the application in the theory of value
    differential calculus requires,
    for the researcher to take some
    additional assumptions. Firstly,
    valued good must be infinite
    divisible, or, what is the same, the function
    utility should be continuous, not
    discrete. This function should be, secondly,
    differentiable, that is, have a tangent in
    every point, and, thirdly, convex, for
    so that the derivative at each point is
    final [See interesting article son
    Menger -- Carl Menger Jr., mathematics
    profession: Menger K. Austrian marginalism and mathematical
    economics. In: Carl Menger and the Austrian School... P. 38--44].

    All
    three additional conditions are introduced for
    convenience of calculation and narrow the range of phenomena,
    explained by marginalist theory. What
    As for infinite divisibility, then this
    property is so uncharacteristic for
    most of the blessings that Jevons and Marshall
    it is necessary to make a reservation that the function
    usefulness refers rather to all of them
    aggregate, and not to one subject (for example,
    to residents of Liverpool or Manchester). But
    for the totality of consumers lose their meaning

    subjective assessments and preferences! Except
    addition, the mathematical version of the theory
    marginal utility means that
    business entity unmistakably finds
    the best option for you
    contrary to the above
    Austrians (primarily Menger) about
    uncertainties and mistakes. Because the
    Austrians avoid drinking
    mathematical analysis, it allows them
    not only cover with your theory more
    a wide range of phenomena, but also to keep it
    consistency and stay within
    somewhat more realistic model
    human behavior [according to the exact
    remark by E. Streisler, for the Austrian
    schools (as opposed to math) in
    the phrase "marginal utility"
    more important noun than adjective
    (Streissler E. What Extent was the Austrian School marginalist? History of
    political economy. Vol.. 4. N 2. P. 426--461)].

    Here
    we come to the next distinctive
    feature of the Austrian school - methodological individualism. All
    economic problems Austrians
    considered and decided at the micro level, at
    individual level. They do not take into account that the whole,
    i.e. society is always greater than the sum of its
    parts, do not recognize specific
    macroeconomic phenomena, irreducible
    to a simple resultant of individual
    preferences and decisions. From our point
    view, this is due to the desire
    Austrians to reveal the essence of phenomena,
    causal relationships and their
    distrust of functional dependencies [cf.
    the very first phrase that Menger begins
    his "Foundations ..." (p. 38). To that
    it should be added that the German term
    "Grenznutzen" can be more accurately translated as "boundary"
    utility, i.e. assessment of the value of a thing
    buyer located at the "border"
    between those who manage to acquire the thing, and
    those who will be forced out of the market; no
    hint at "limit" in mathematical
    there is no sense of the word here. In this sense
    the Austrians are closer to K. Marx than to
    most economists and mathematicians
    who adhered to positivist
    views.

    IN
    connections with methodological individualism
    is also a remarkable absence in
    works of Austrian marginalists
    developed ideas of balance. It is clear that
    Walrasian concept of general equilibrium
    was too much for the Austrians
    supra-individual, requiring excessive
    rationality and optimality of solutions.
    Much more interesting is that in Menger's theory
    the concepts of partial
    equilibrium, the only equilibrium price.

    important
    role in the Austrian theory is occupied by the factor
    time. Less than all other marginalists
    the Austrians deserved a reproach for purely
    static point of view. They didn't forget
    emphasize that value judgments
    people are directly dependent on
    what time period they can calculate
    satisfaction of their needs ("period
    prudence"). It is the factor
    time and associated uncertainty
    lead to errors of exchange participants and not
    allow the general balance to be established,
    inherent in the timeless system of Walras,
    where all prices and quantities of goods are determined
    simultaneously.

    Now
    we have to give a group portrait of three
    founders of the Austrian school, works
    which are presented in this book. In their
    biographies have a lot in common: all three
    come from noble families, studied at
    Faculty of Law, Vienna
    university, entered the state
    service, then alternated teaching in
    university with important positions in
    Austrian state (Böhm-Bawerk three times
    was finance minister
    Supreme Court of Appeal and
    President of the Academy of Sciences, Vizer - Minister of Commerce), were
    life members of the upper house
    parliament. They were connected by friends, and Böhm-Bawerka
    and Vizer - even family relations.

    IN
    areas of economic theory are all the same,
    certainly were close ideological
    associates. However, history has
    each of them has its own role, and it is precisely this "specialization" that
    in our opinion, the Austrian school is obliged
    early flowering and noticeable influence.

    Group
    Austrian limit theorists
    usefulness deserves the name of the school
    primarily because she had a teacher with
    unquestioned scientific authority - Karl
    Menger (1840-1921). When being unknown
    young (31 years old) civil servants and
    journalist, he decided to become a Privatdozent
    University of Vienna and as
    just made recommendations
    published book "Foundations of political
    economy", no one, of course, could think
    that this work for more than a hundred years
    will be the main source of ideas for economists
    Austrian school. Menger has practically no
    there were teachers, although there were predecessors:
    based mainly on German literature,
    he was not, however, familiar with the writings
    Gossen and Thunen, in which the ideas of the limit
    utility and marginal
    performance have found their most
    early incarnation. At the same time almost
    unable to find any idea or
    concept of Böhm-Bawerk, Wieser and their
    followers that were not anticipated
    separate provisions and even footnotes from the "Foundations
    political economy". Actually
    saying everything that was said above about
    characteristic features of the Austrian
    schools as a whole, especially in
    most related to the masterpiece
    Menger. It is all the more surprising that this
    books had a very difficult fate. First
    publication went virtually unnoticed [if,
    of course, not to consider such attentive
    readers like Böhm-Bawerk, Wieser and Marshall!].
    The second edition of "Foundations ..." is out
    only in 1923, after the death of the author, when
    the main ideas of the Austrian school have already become
    widely known in a more accessible
    interpretations of Böhm-Bawerk and Wieser. On
    the international language of economists is English
    - the book has been translated
    80 years after it was written.

    IN
    result for almost a century after
    publication of "Foundations ..." Menger
    remained more revered than read
    author. Resurgence of widespread interest
    economists since the 1970s. to ideas
    Menger we owe to F. Hayek, who did not
    only gave many of them further
    development, but also did extremely much for
    their propaganda and memorialization
    founder of the Austrian school.

    Eugene
    (correct Eugen) von Böhm-Bawerk (1851--1914)
    played a different role in the history of the Austrian school
    role. Unlike Menger, he was at first
    the turn of a statesman of the highest
    rank (a list of his positions is given above),
    giving away the remaining free time
    teaching. As for deep and
    leisurely research work, then on
    She had almost no time left. Not
    by chance all significant works of Böhm-Bawerk
    were written by him for the first, relatively
    quiet ten years of his career (1880--1889),
    when he taught at Innsbruck
    university: in 1881 his dissertation was published
    "Rights and relations from the point of view of the doctrine
    about national economic benefits"; in 1884 - the first part of the main work "Capital and
    profit", which criticized
    previous theories of capital and
    percent; in 1886 -- published in our
    collection of work "Fundamentals of the theory of value
    economic benefits "; in 1889 - the second part
    "Capital and profits" -- "Positive
    theory of capital"; in 1890 - the book "K
    completion of the Marxist system,
    to which Böhm-Bawerk was one of the first to subject
    criticism of Marx's theory of value, citing
    on the contradiction between the I and III volumes of "Capital".
    The pace taken by Böhm-Bawerk during these years,
    impressive, but he certainly should have
    badly affect the depth, thoughtfulness and
    completion of his work. Not
    by chance it was Böhm-Bawerk, and not Menger
    was (and still is) the main
    the target of criticism of the Austrian school in general.
    But insufficient finishing of their own
    theoretical research (especially tangible
    in "Capital and profit") did not prevent Böhm-Bawerk
    perform another important function:
    eloquent promoter of ideas
    Austrian school (primarily Menger),
    as well as skillful and temperamental
    polemicist who defends them in the fight against
    competing theories. It is in this
    as Böhm-Bawerk acquired a wide
    fame in the scientific world (it is no coincidence that
    in our literature, beginning with the "Political
    economy of rentier" by N. I. Bukharin, it was he who
    was proclaimed the head of the Austrian school [see.
    See also: Economic Encyclopedia.
    Political Economy. T. 1. M.: Soviet
    encyclopedia, 1972, p. 152]). Selected for
    publications in our collection of work
    allows the reader to compose the most
    a complete picture of Böhm-Bawerk as
    popularizer and polemicist [most
    Böhm-Bawerk's significant research in
    areas of theory ("Capital and Profit")
    currently being prepared for release in
    one of the publishers]. Böhm-Bawerk was
    a lawyer not only by education, but also by
    way of thinking and style of presentation. He
    striving for clarity, persuasiveness and
    intelligibility of the argument and was not inclined
    to careful and comprehensive consideration
    each definition in the spirit of Menger, who
    brought laconicism and elegance of style to
    sacrifice of meaning. This distinction is good
    transmitted in Russian translation. Reader,
    who wants to make an initial
    introduction to the main ideas
    Austrian school, can in principle start
    precisely from the work of Böhm-Bawerk.

    Third
    from the authors presented in our collection
    is Baron Friedrich von Wieser (1851--1926). He
    more than two of his colleagues contributed
    the design of the Austrian school in
    school - being the most capable of them
    teacher, he devoted 42 years of his life
    exposition of the Austrian theory with
    professorship (first in Prague in 1884-1902, and then in Vienna, where he inherited
    Menger's pulpit), and also wrote the first
    systematized treatise-textbook
    Austrian school - "Theory
    public economy" (1914). Contribution
    Wieser into the Austrian theory is very
    peculiar. First, he became famous for
    that gave bright names and memorable
    formulations of many of the ideas of marginalism.
    It was he who first used the terms "limiting
    utility" (Grenznutzen), "imputation"
    (Zurechnung), "Gossen's laws".

    Secondly,
    it was Wieser who was the first to succeed [in the works
    "On the origin and fundamental laws
    economic value" (1884) and "Natural
    value" (1889)] to formulate the principle
    lost profits, giving purely
    subjective explanation of costs, and
    elaborate the theory
    imputation inferring value
    productive goods from their value
    consumable product, and for the first time
    state the central principle
    equality of marginal products,
    produced by this productive
    good in all its applications [as B.
    Seligman, Wieser's task was
    extending Menger's ideas to spheres
    production and distribution. (Seligman B.
    The main currents of modern
    economic thought. M.: Progress, 1968. S. 168)].

    Third,
    from the early representatives of the Austrian school
    only Wieser tried to connect ideas
    marginal utility with capabilities
    the most appropriate organization
    society as a whole. Wieser can be called
    least "analytical" and most
    prone to synthesis, descriptive and
    sociological approach
    Austrian school. In this sense, he
    closest to the German historical
    school. Unlike Menger and Böhm-Bawerk,
    former staunch liberals, Wieser
    tried to justify the need
    government intervention and
    central planning (the term "planning"
    he again used for the first time in Western
    economic theory) in order to
    implement the principles of marginal utility in
    life and ensure optimal
    the functioning of the economy (his youthful
    adherence to the ideas of socialism, as well as
    passion for fascism in old age,
    obviously not a coincidence).

    let's move on
    to a more detailed description
    published in the collection of works.

    TO.
    Menger. Foundations of Political Economy
    (Grundsatze der Volkswirtschaftslehre) [this title, as we
    seems to be more accurate
    conveys the content of the book than literal
    translation: "Fundamentals of the doctrine of folk
    economy"].

    Mentioned
    above the "revered-unreadable" paradox
    this book, in our opinion, is not accidental, its
    reasons are rooted in some features
    Menger's work for which you want
    draw the attention of the reader.

    Before
    In general, it should be noted that the book has
    subtitle: "General part". This
    means that we are dealing with an introductory part
    to a much larger work, Menger, so
    just like Marx, was essentially a man
    one book, which was supposed to contain
    a coherent and comprehensive system of categories
    economy. Working on it (and not
    written) treatise, he devoted a large
    part of his life (since 1903 he even left for
    this his professorial chair in
    university). Menger did not agree to
    reprint and translation of "Foundations ..." to
    as long as they are carefully recycled
    and supplemented, will not take their place in his
    general theoretical system.

    Except
    in addition, faced with misunderstanding and
    by the hostile reaction of German economists,
    which at that time were under strong
    influence of anti-theoretical
    neohistorical school and its head Schmoller,
    Menger was forced to join him in
    martial arts on the methodological front.
    His second major work "Research
    on the method of the social sciences and political
    economy in particular" (1833) not only
    contained a polemic with the inductive
    methodology of the historical school, but also
    disclosed the main methodological
    principles of Menger himself [chief among them
    is that economics
    should identify the simplest, typical
    elements of reality and ascend from them to
    more complex phenomena, where the action of precise
    the laws of the theory are difficult to recognize due to
    influence of non-economic motives]. unfolded after that
    fierce polemic with Schmoller,
    entered the history of economics as
    "method dispute" [cf. about this controversy and
    various assessments: Bostaph S. The Methodological Debate
    Between Carl Menger and the German Historicists (Atlantic Economic Journal.
    1978.V.VI. N 3. P. 3--16)], Menger gave enough
    a lot of strength meant to write
    proposed treatise.

    All
    the foregoing does not allow for
    "Grounds..." Menger's requirements,
    which the completed
    theoretical system, for example
    criticize them for a very narrow circle
    issues raised: values, prices,
    origin and essence of money. Besides,
    the style itself is important, in which
    written "Foundations ...". Trying
    state the most general principles of
    theory, Menger studiously avoids
    excessive detail and categorization,
    leaving an explanation of many specific
    questions for later [judging by the preparatory
    materials, Menger was going to dedicate
    the second part of his treatise on research
    interest, wages, rent, credit and
    paper money; the third part is "applied"
    theories industrial production And
    trade; fourth - criticism of modern
    him an economic system and proposals
    for her reform. (Hayek F. von Carl Menger. In: Menger C. Principles of
    economics. N. Y.-L., 1981. P. 16)]. This creates
    the impression that he foresaw those
    contradictions that can confuse
    his theory in a more crude, popular
    interpretation. It's somewhere deep
    thoughtful, and somewhere, maybe
    intuitive foresight combined with
    impressive internal logic and
    sequence of presentation led to
    to what is against the "Foundations ..." Menger
    it is impossible to put forward a majority
    critical arguments that are usually
    speak out against his "inconsistent
    followers "- Böhm-Bawerk and Wieser. Not
    accidentally building a new austrian theory
    Mises, Hayek and others built the main
    way on Menger's foundation,
    abandoning many concepts of his
    students. We will now make a short
    journey through the Foundations of Political
    savings", focusing only on those
    moments that distinguish Menger from his
    predecessors or contemporaries or
    had a significant impact on his
    followers. As for the
    logical connection of arguments, then it
    stated by the author so clearly and clearly,
    which does not need, in our opinion, special
    comments.

    "Foundations..."
    consist of three major sections. First of
    them (chapters one - three) is devoted
    cornerstone of Austrian theory - the doctrine of subjective value. But
    I wonder what the third chapter is where,
    in fact, it contains the theory of value,
    the author prefaces two preparatory
    chapters (about 1/4 of the entire book!), devoted to
    the doctrine of goods in general, and economic
    blessings in particular. In defining the first
    Menger stresses the importance of cognition
    man of their useful properties.
    The characteristic of the latter is their
    rare but curious what Menger avoids
    pronounce this term because
    economic good does not absolute
    rare, and exceeding the planned
    need for a good or "necessary
    quantities" (specifically Menger's
    category denoting quantitatively
    specific need of the individual
    some foreseeable period) over
    the amount of this good, which, as
    the individual expects will be available to him. So,
    already in the first definitions one can see
    Menger's general style of research: rejection
    use of short but meaningful
    terms, the desire to give as much as possible
    adequate, albeit wordy, presentation
    thoughts. Some of the most famous ideas
    the first section concern the division of all goods
    for the benefits of higher and lower orders, as well as
    the principle of complementarity (additionality)
    productive goods. Consistently
    climbing up the river of time from my own
    starting point -- satisfaction
    needs, Menger first explained
    value of productive goods
    produced with their help consumer
    good, and not vice versa, as it was with the authors,
    explaining value in terms of cost
    production. For Menger, costs are valuable only
    in the event that with their help
    produced a product of value.
    Recall, by the way, that the same problem
    consumer evaluation of produced
    costs through the cost of the product - socially necessary costs
    - saw and
    tried to solve K. Marx in the third volume of "Capital",
    in the chapter on market price and market
    cost. (An interesting example of how
    authors coming from completely different
    prerequisites often come to very
    similar conclusions!) Principle
    complementarity enriches the picture
    with new colors: it turns out that
    productive goods may depreciate
    and even cease to be good if
    missing at least one required "accessory"
    element from that set of performance
    goods that are necessary for a certain
    production process (output,
    unthinkable for cost theory). Development
    Menger problems of complementarity, and
    also (later) changing proportions, in
    which can be connected
    productive goods, testifies to
    that the founder of the Austrian school
    much deeper than Jevons and Walras reflected
    in his theory, the sphere of production and,
    therefore, his theory does not
    deserved the title of "political economy
    rentier", for which "production,
    labor involved in obtaining
    material wealth lies out of sight"
    [Bukharin N.I. Political economy of rentier.
    M.: Orbita, 1988. S. 19--20].

    Draws
    attention to yourself" 4 of the first chapter, in its entirety
    dedicated to the importance of the time factor and
    the uncertainty it causes for
    economic activity of people.
    Focused in this paragraph, as well as
    statements scattered throughout the book
    leaves no doubt that the approach
    Menger to the economy can not be called
    static and timeless (as opposed to
    approach of Jevons or Walras). If
    conceived Menger's treatise was written, we
    most likely would have received a non-static
    equilibrium model, and the theory of economic
    activity as a process taking place in
    time and space.

    In
    the second chapter we want to pay attention
    reader to a vivid example of Menger's
    methodological monism: from
    relative rarity of goods (see explanation
    above) Menger deduced human egoism, and
    also a property phenomenon! (See pp. 78, 82).
    The analysis of the transfer of goods from
    economic to non-economic, and
    vice versa (pp. 82--87). Here, as in some
    subsequent places, there is a noticeable tendency
    Menger to historical research
    economic institutions. Really,
    uncompromising struggle against "vices"
    historicism", absolutization of descriptive
    and inductive methods did not exclude either
    Menger, nor his followers
    respect for economic
    history (about this, in particular,
    bear witness to the dedication of the "Foundations..."
    V. Roscher - the head of the German historical
    schools). This also distinguishes the Austrian
    school from other areas of marginalism (for
    except for Marshall).

    Chapter
    the third is central in the whole book, it
    contains the theory of subjective value. IN
    difference from other marginalists Menger
    determined the value of goods not by quantity
    the benefits they bring, and in importance
    the needs they satisfy. This,
    seemingly insignificant difference in
    actually plays an important role. It
    indicates that Menger: 1)
    develops a theory that later
    called the ordinal version
    marginalism: the need for each good is not
    has an absolute value, and is expressed
    only in comparison with the usefulness of another
    goods (the figures in his tables are conditional
    character and express not magnitude, but hierarchy
    needs -- see note. us. 156); 2) not
    connects, unlike Jevons, his theory
    values ​​with a hedonistic interpretation
    human nature, going back to Bentham (for
    this to the marginalists who claimed to
    explanation of "psychology"
    business entity, got a lot
    from contemporaries-psychologists [See. details:
    Avtonomov V. S. Search for new ways//Origins.
    1990. "2. S. 187--188]). It must be said that Menger
    did not use at all when building my own
    theory of the term "utility".

    Along the way
    Menger decides for a long time existed in
    economic theory paradox: the most
    beneficial to human life
    are not always the most
    valuable. He does this by pointing out that
    value is given by people only
    economic, i.e. relatively rare,
    blessings.

    Draws
    attention to the categoricalness with which
    Menger advocates a purely subjective
    the nature of value (p. 101) that does not exist outside
    people (recall that for supporters
    objective theories, including those of Marx,
    "values" or "values" are often
    used as a synonym for goods
    regardless of the presence of the needy
    subject).

    Outlining
    his formulation of the principles of diminishing
    the importance of gratified utilities and
    equal importance of all satisfied
    needs (corresponding to I and II laws
    Gossen), Menger places the second of them in
    footnote as a special case of the first (p. 109). For
    of all general equilibrium theorists this
    principle, on the contrary, is decisive.

    Most
    Menger's argument looks strained,
    consistently coming from satisfaction
    needs, where this motive is obviously
    does not play a dominant role. Indicative in
    In this sense, the paragraph "On Productivity
    capital", where Menger passes
    abstract as from the motive of accumulation
    capital, and from specifically
    entrepreneurial motives,
    later investigated by I. Schumpeter in "Theory
    economic development"[Schumpeter J.
    Theory of economic development. M.:
    Progress, 1982. S. 193].

    IN
    this chapter Menger for the first time in the economic
    literature assumes that
    that a certain amount of product can
    be produced using various
    combinations of productive goods (pp. 139--140).
    This idea of ​​substitution of productive goods
    (which was abandoned by Menger's successors
    Böhm-Bawerk and Wieser) later received in
    Western economic thought significant
    development, and in particular underlies the theory
    production functions.

    IN
    his theory of the value of productive
    blessings Menger takes another bold step - he refuses to distinguish between three
    main factors of production: land,
    labor and capital. This long tradition
    violates on the grounds that the value
    all kinds of goods, including land and labor,
    determined on the basis of the same
    the principle he formulated - the value of their
    products. At the same time, Menger again shows
    its anti-hedonistic orientation and
    criticizes a common theory (for example,
    Jevons), according to which a person,
    laborer is compensated for
    discomfort associated with it (p. 146).

    But,
    perhaps the most important in terms of
    further development of Western
    economic theory was the following contribution
    Menger. Talking about the factors that determine
    the value of goods of higher orders, Menger (on. p.
    140--141) sets out an idea that later
    most thoroughly developed Wieser. This
    principle of "lost profits" ("opportunity
    cost"), which entered the arsenal of the most
    important tools of modern
    microeconomic theory. According to
    Menger the value of a productive good
    determined by the difference between the value
    product, which is planned with its help
    produce, and the value of others,
    satisfying less important needs
    goods that could be produced
    alternative use of this
    productive good.

    Second
    section "Foundations ..." includes chapters
    fourth and fifth. Its content is a transition
    from subjective value to price, i.e. to
    exchange proportion of goods. Relationship between
    the second and first sections are the relation
    phenomena to essence ["Prices are the only
    sensible elements of everything
    process..." (p. 163)]. Menger
    consistently displays prices from
    individual, subjective values, but
    takes into account the objective influence
    environment -- various types of exchange. First step,
    which he demands from Menger
    subjectivist approach,
    preconditions for an equivalent exchange. After all
    this premise implies equality
    good for some objectively inherent in them
    the indicator itself. Menger takes this step
    stating that the exchange cannot be
    equivalent because it is always beneficial
    to both of its participants: after him their
    needs are better met
    than before him (pp. 150-151). Note that this conclusion
    absolutely inevitably follows from the chosen
    the author of the prerequisites:
    meet the needs of both
    sole motive of any economic
    activities. (In Marx's "Capital" in
    exchange analysis is implicitly laid down
    prerequisite for the existence of capital and
    the dominant role of the accumulation motive
    capital, which breaks out into
    chapter 4 of the first volume. One for all capitalists
    hoarding motive by its very nature
    presupposes the commensurability of goods. At
    Menger, the benefits are objectively incommensurable:
    how many people, so many values
    given quantity of goods.)

    Action
    This prerequisite is also manifested in
    determining the boundaries of the exchange: if further
    exchange will no longer improve satisfaction
    the needs of its members,
    will cease (see pp. 155-156). (For comparison:
    Marx, the boundaries of exchange are the boundaries
    production, and not vice versa, but the latter in
    in turn are established only by the possibility
    continuation and acceleration of the process
    accumulation, the very same motive for accumulation
    nature is limitless. As for
    accumulation possibilities, they are given
    solvent demand, and
    the only factor affecting
    the last one is income.) It's easy
    note that the "needs-based" approach
    fully rehabilitates such an important area
    economic activities such as trade.
    Classics and Marxists, as you know,
    denied the productive nature of labor in
    this industry, leaving behind only
    redistribution of what is produced.
    Some provisions read today as
    a hot-button argument in defense of trade
    intermediaries appropriate in our current
    parliamentary debates.

    I want to
    also note two modest in scope, but not
    by value, fragment. The first is about "economic
    sacrifices required by barter transactions"
    (p. 161). Here, if you wish, you can see
    the beginnings of the concept of "transactional
    costs "playing in modern
    Western neo-institutionalist
    literature an outstanding role [Kapelyushnikov R.
    I. Economic theory of property rights.
    M.: IMEMO, 1990. S. 28--37]. The other is the first
    theoretical economic literature
    distinction between demand prices and prices
    proposal (20 years before Marshall) which,
    no doubt was prompted to Menger by his
    the practice of a stock observer.

    Main
    part of chapter five is devoted to education
    prices in various conditions - at
    isolated exchange, monopoly of the seller and
    buyer competition and, finally, with
    bilateral competition. Draws on itself
    attention to the order of analysis in which
    logical transition does not come from free
    competition to monopoly (as in all
    modern Western textbooks), but vice versa.
    This, of course, did not mean that Menger
    proceeded from the existence of real
    giant capitalist monopolies
    late XIX - early XX century. This
    the sequence is dictated to the author: 1)
    the methodology of research chosen by him - from
    simplest cases to more and more complex ones; 2)
    penchant for historical parallels (and
    historically relatively free
    competition is definitely
    late stage product
    commodity exchange) (see pp. 183-184) and 3) the same
    pervasive subjectivism: the simplest
    for Menger is the case when we have
    dealing with value judgments of one
    buyer and one seller; harder if
    several buyers participate in the exchange;
    even harder if sellers too
    several, because the theorist needs
    "get into the soul" of each of the participants
    exchange and ferret out its subjective
    preferences. Interestingly, the price
    are determined according to Menger in both monopoly and
    competitive situation, the same laws
    subjective value, but these laws
    appear under monopoly and under
    competition in completely different
    the seller's policy: in case of competition, he
    it is unprofitable to keep the goods and resort to
    price discrimination of buyers.
    Menger's theory of price from all others
    options for marginalism distinguishes
    the absence of a clear concept
    determined equilibrium price: market
    Menger's price can fluctuate between
    estimates of the unit of the good the least strong of
    competitors who have entered into an exchange and the most
    strong of those who could not do it
    do (pp. 175--176). The more competitors, the
    already room for price fluctuations, but all
    equals some part of the price in each case
    explained not by the factor of subjective
    values, but the ability to bargain.

    Important
    mediating link in the transition from
    original abstraction of the individual
    economy, aimed at direct
    consumption, to a developed exchange
    economy, typical of
    capitalist economy, is
    Menger's doctrine of consumer and exchange
    the value of the good. Both the one and the other are pure for him
    subjective quantities (exchange value
    good is the value of other goods that
    can be obtained in return). If exchange
    the value of a person's wealth
    more consumer, exchange can
    happen if the opposite is not the case. Ratio
    same use and exchange value
    determined by the quantity of the good,
    at the disposal of that person.
    Thus, for large owners,
    such as manufacturers, prevailing, or
    "economic", in the words of Menger,
    should invariably be exchangeable, and not
    the use value of their
    goods. So, Menger corrects the accepted
    them for the predominant consumer motive
    economic activity without violating
    same time of their original premises.

    Finally,
    the last section of the book (chapters seven and
    eighth) is devoted to the essence of money and their
    origin. These questions are always
    worried Menger both in theory (among his
    few works included two
    articles (1892 and 1900) on money for the Handbook
    in state sciences", and for
    second edition of the handbook article was
    completely revised), and in practice
    (in the same 1892, Menger was a member of the Imperial
    commission on monetary reform and played in it
    main role). Menger's approach to essence
    money is also peculiar - it takes her out of
    various "ability of goods to be sold"
    (Absatzfahigkeit). Here we are dealing with purely
    Menger category, which can be
    it would be most accurate to translate into
    modern language as "liquidity".
    Menger means the ability of a product
    always find a sale in any quantity, in
    extreme case with a slight loss in value (p.
    213). The most liquid commodity becomes
    money.

    Factor
    sales ability has such a large
    meaning that the exchange can not be started
    in order to better meet the needs,
    but for the sake of obtaining a more exchangeable good.
    It is easy to see that Menger is here
    rises to the next level
    specifying the motives of economic
    activities, taking into account the realities of monetary
    economy.

    Job
    E. Böhm-Bawerka "Fundamentals of the Theory of Value
    economic benefits" for the first time was
    published in 1886 in a German magazine
    "Conrads Jahrbucher für Nationalokonomie und Statistik". This
    first contact of the representative
    Austrian school directly to
    German readers (recall that it is in
    this time the "dispute about the method" raged,
    which ended with "organizational conclusions" - the supporters of the Austrian school had
    prohibited from holding professorships in
    Germany). In this work, as noted
    Soviet researcher I. G. Blyumin, "Bohm-Bawerk
    made it very clear
    an exposition of the theory of value of the Austrians ... C
    with good reason, the "Austrians" could
    say: "Die, but it is better not to Böhm-Bawerk
    about the theory of marginal utility
    [Bohm-Bawerk E. Fundamentals of the theory of value
    economic benefits. M.-L. 1929. S. IV].

    To
    avoid repeats, we'll stop here
    only at those moments where Böhm-Bawerk contributes
    something new compared to Menger's theory.

    WITH
    the first pages are clearly visible
    Böhm-Bawerk's desire to bring more
    strong bridges between the theory of subjective
    Menger-Wiser values ​​and objective
    price proportions, developing on
    market. For this, Böhm-Bawerk calls
    exchange value objective value,
    inherent in material goods themselves (p. 249).
    Recall that Menger did not consider the exchange
    value is an objective property of goods themselves:
    in his interpretation, exchange value is
    subjective value of goods that can be
    get in exchange for what you already have. Rigid
    separation of subjective and objective
    values ​​will affect Böhm-Bawerk and
    later. It suffices to point to the structure
    book in which the author distinguishes two parts:
    the theory of subjective value and the theory
    objective exchange value.

    IN
    the first part of the innovations introduced by Böhm-Bawerk,
    are. Thinking about a hierarchical scale
    needs (p. 274), he strengthens her
    realism in what makes the table
    omissions as some needs
    can only be fully satisfied, not
    parts (this is the next step after Menger,
    removing the Austrian theory of value from
    mathematical version of marginalism). Böhm-Bawerk
    gives a clear definition of subjective
    the value of goods through its marginal utility (p.
    285). It should be noted that this translation
    conveys the meaning more precisely than the conventional
    teachings of the Austrian school. usefulness
    (Nutzlichkeit) the Austrians call the characteristic
    of this kind of goods in general, benefit (Nutzen)
    - a characteristic of a certain amount

    this good.

    own
    Böhm-Bawerk's contribution is also his attempt
    find the proportion between
    the total value of these goods and the marginal
    usefulness (pp. 286--287). Böhm-Bawerk believes that
    marginal utilities of individual units
    of this good have the property
    additivity, but not multiplicativity.
    The marginal utility of units of a given
    stock (of the same quality) in case
    summation will not be the same, since
    they are designed to satisfy
    needs of varying importance. (Happening,
    when goods are originally intended for
    sales, Böhm-Bawerk considers separately
    and multiplicativity is allowed there.)
    It should be noted that the provisional
    Menger avoided this problem altogether.
    He understands the concepts of wealth and property
    before determining the value of goods and not
    returns to them later. Wherein
    Menger insisted on relative, not on
    the absolute nature of value and not
    assumed the possibility of its measurement in
    any units. Böhm-Bawerk, trying
    quantify the overall value,
    compelled, without proper reason, to proceed from
    measurability of value, i.e. move to
    more vulnerable to criticism of the cardinal
    versions of marginalism [deep criticism
    Böhm-Bawerk's teachings on measurability
    value was given by an outstanding Russian economist
    Slutsky E. Zur Kritik des Bohm-Baverkschen Wertbegriffs
    und seiner Lehre von der Messbarkeit des Wertes//Schmollers Jahrbuch. V.LI. N
    4. S. 37--52)].

    Most
    this is clearly stated in chapter three,
    where Böhm-Bawerk asks himself the question: "We can
    whether we determine the magnitude of this difference (between
    sensations) more precisely, can we express it in
    numbers?" (p. 303) and gives him
    affirmative answer.

    At
    he refers to the fact that we have to
    countless times to choose between
    one large and many small
    pleasures, although this is obviously not at all
    proves the measurability of value in
    absolute values. Postulating such
    way "digital determination of the value
    pleasures and hardships" (p. 304), Böhm-Bawerk
    turns out to be much closer to Jevons and even
    Bentham with his "arithmetic of happiness",
    than to Menger [Avtonomov V. S. Model
    man in the bourgeois political
    savings from Smith to Marshall // Origins. 1989."
    1. S. 204--219. This is also evidenced by
    Böhm-Bawerk's use of the hedonistic
    terminology that Menger avoided].

    Trying
    bring the theory of subjective value closer to
    conditions of "developed exchange relations",
    Böhm-Bawerk draws to explain
    individual difficult cases concept
    substitutional marginal utility. Author
    concludes that the value
    man's lost winter coat
    in most cases, it is not measured
    marginal utility, and marginal
    the usefulness of other goods that will have to
    do not buy or sell to buy
    coat to replace the lost one. She is in her
    turn depends on the price of the coat on the market (than
    it is more expensive, the greater the loss of other benefits).
    So ultimately
    the subjective value of the product
    determined by its price. This logical
    the circle has long been
    main target for Marxist critics
    Austrian theory (starting with Hilferding
    and Bukharin). To Menger, a similar criticism
    inapplicable, since it has the value of goods
    determined only by the intensity
    need and the presence of the good, and in no way
    depends on the price.

    That
    the same can be said about Böhm-Bawerk's addiction
    values ​​from "the relationship between demand and
    supply", wealth or poverty
    human (pp. 294--295).

    Main
    Böhm-Bawerk's contribution to world science is the idea of
    that the ever-existing difference
    between the value of a product and its determinants
    the total cost of production (ie.
    e. profit) depends on the duration
    production period (pp. 327--328). On this
    thesis, Böhm-Bawerk built the theory
    capital, profit and interest in his work
    "Capital and profit" (part II).

    Big
    of interest is also the attempt by Böhm-Bawerk
    combine the law of subjective value with
    the law of production costs (p. 333). Author
    recognizes the status of the law of costs
    rules by which in private
    case of unlimited possibilities
    actual increase in production
    it is possible to measure the value of "highly useful"
    product, although the costs themselves are ultimately
    account are determined by the value of the least
    useful (marginal) product.

    big
    significance for substantiating not only the Böhm-Bawerk theory,
    but of the whole marginalist theory of value
    has a small seventh chapter. Here Böhm-Bawerk
    responds to accusations of unrealism
    marginalist model of man,
    doing a huge amount
    cumbersome calculations to
    determine the value of goods (especially "remote
    order"). The author's counterarguments (which
    repeated with slight variations
    supporters of the marginalist - neoclassical theory to this day)
    are:

    1. by habit and skill most
      calculations of this kind are done almost
      instantly, albeit approximately.
      Excessive prudence is even unprofitable
      - it takes too much time and effort
      [at this point it is clearly manifested
      superiority of the Austrian school, not
      requiring absolute rationality and
      optimal choice, over mathematical
      version of marginalism. Representatives
      the latter were able to build this conclusion into their
      theory only more than 70 years after
      this work of Böhm-Bawerk (Stigler G. The economics of
      information//Journal of Political Economy. 1961. V. 69. P. 213--245)];
    2. in most cases, a new calculation at all
      do not have to do, because the information
      about the value of this thing is already laid
      in our memory [curiously, exactly like
      the same considerations Marx in the third volume of "Capital"
      explained the determination of prices by producers with
      taking into account compensation for the conditions of production,
      different from the average (Marx K., Engels F.
      Op. 2nd ed. T. 25. Part I. S. 221--236)];
    3. finally, a developed system of division of labor
      allows the producer or owner of goods
      distant order, take into account only the exchange

    the value of your good, leaving everything
    other stages of production and evaluation on
    share of the following entrepreneurs.

    Second
    part of the book -- "The Theory of Objective Exchange
    cost" differs from the presentation of those
    the same questions by Menger as follows.
    Above all Böhm-Bawerk from the very beginning
    brings theoretical analysis closer to
    modern reality and expresses
    subjective values ​​of goods in terms of money (he
    has the right to do so because he previously declared
    about the measurability of value). Problems
    monopolies and imperfect competition at
    teachers are much deeper than
    student: buyers, according to Menger, can
    buy yourself not one horse, but several:
    examines the impact of change
    proposals not only on price, but also on
    the number of those who bought (from Böhm-Bawerk
    the last one is fixed), etc.

    IN
    the same time the case is bilateral
    competition at Böhm-Bawerk dismantled
    much deeper (chapter four
    second part).

    Before
    of all it should be noted that since Böhm-Bawerk
    unlike Menger considers
    a situation of developed commodity exchange,
    mediated by money, it includes
    considering the subjective value of money
    for buyers of different levels
    solvency (relative to the available
    them needs). Interestingly, with
    This argument he tries to refute (p.
    388--391) optimality of the competitive
    equilibrium from the point of view of the whole society (this
    the idea is central to the theory
    general equilibrium since Walras).
    So we have every right
    call Böhm-Bawerk a fighter against the "bourgeois
    apologetics!

    largest
    theoretical interest, from our point of view,
    represents a logical circle analysis,
    arising from the explanation of the price
    subjective value, while
    the latter "if there is an open
    market" is determined by the market price (pp. 394-400). Here we see that Böhm-Bawerk
    aware of the existence of this
    problems and tried to solve them. He thought,
    that the market price is the price at which
    the buyer only hopes to purchase the goods
    in the future, but since it is the future
    rather vaguely, the evaluation of the good is still
    may be revised. At the same time, in all
    cases, the boundary of its price will still be "immediate
    the ultimate utility of a given thing" (p. 397).
    It cannot be said that the Böhm-Bawerk solution
    really unleashed this Gordian
    node. After all, the market price turns into "hope"
    only in very specific markets.
    For example, on commodity or stock exchanges,
    where there are constant price fluctuations,
    or in the market for productive goods,
    whose value really depends on
    how much demand there will be
    use produced with their help
    product. (We argue here in terms of
    the Austrian theory of value itself.) On those
    same consumer "open" markets,
    where the price at any given moment can be
    quite a stable guideline for
    consumer, marginal utility theory
    really "slips", with this
    it's nothing you can do.

    Two
    final chapters of Böhm-Bawerk's work
    devoted to highly inventive attempts
    built into the Austrian theory of the subjective
    values ​​are different, alternative explanations
    of the same phenomenon: "the law of supply and
    demand" and "the law of production costs".
    From our point of view, Böhm-Bawerk contributes
    useful clarifications in the concepts of demand and
    sentences: classical theory understood
    them as simple quantities of commodities, he
    considers it necessary to correct these
    quantities, given the intensity of desire
    buy a product even at a high price and desire

    sell it even at a low price.

    We advise
    The reader should also note that
    theory of subjective value as opposed to
    "objective" theories explains such
    phenomena like markdowns, cheap
    sales, etc., in which the goods
    are sold below production costs (p.
    412--413).

    "Theory
    public economy" F. von Wieser
    (1914) ranks in the history of the Austrian school
    about the same place as "The Basics
    political economy" by J. S. Mill in
    history of the English classical
    political economy. This is the "end of the system",
    ordering different ideas of different
    authors, an eclectic desire for
    compromises, maximum expansion
    object of study, sometimes at the expense of
    less depth of research (especially for
    compared with Menger's Foundations).

    For
    of this collection, we have chosen two fragments
    from Wieser's voluminous treatise. First of
    them continues and develops the theory of value
    Menger-Böhm-Bawerk and allows the reader
    get a complete picture of
    Austrian theory of value in general. Second
    the fragment, on the other hand, does not find any
    parallels in Menger and Böhm-Bawerk and
    introduces Wieser to us as a thinker,
    the most intense
    institutional and sociological
    questions.

    IN
    the first fragment we published (" 16--25)
    contains all the main
    improvements that Wieser made to
    Austrian theory of value. Wherein
    draws attention to the fact that all
    Wieser's achievements are on the line
    approximations of the abstract Mengerian
    analysis to economic practice. So,
    It is for these reasons that Wieser
    strongly rejects the additive method
    determining the total utility of a given
    stock of goods when each unit has it
    different marginal utility, and
    advocates a multiplicative way when
    marginal utility is simply multiplied by
    number of similar goods. Next, draws
    attention to detail
    ratio between own limit
    the usefulness of the product and the cost of
    production (understood as the largest
    utility of other goods that could be
    made with these tools.
    production). Wieser proves that
    in most cases these values
    quite close and interchangeable,
    however, there are times when
    change in the stock of goods or
    need for them can lead to their
    sharp divergence. In these cases
    value is determined not by cost, but by
    own marginal utility of the good. .

    next,
    and perhaps the most important contribution
    Wieser in Austrian economic theory
    school is his solution to the problem
    income distribution. In order to
    solve this problem, Vizer creates
    theory of imputation set forth in "20-23. Menger
    trying to determine the contribution of each of
    means of production into final income
    through a thought experiment:
    estimated how income would decrease due to
    loss of this productive good,
    when other complementary goods will
    other uses have been found. Vizer believes
    this technique is artificial and ns
    relevant economic practice (to
    In addition, in this case, the total income,
    pertaining to all factors of production,
    will be less than the value of the product). His
    the solution is perhaps closer to Walrasian: we
    must find a few relatives
    products (i.e. produced with
    the same productive goods)
    valued on the market at marginal
    utility, and construct a system of equations
    values ​​in which the number of equations (products)
    will equal the number of unknowns
    production factors. Solving this system
    the observer theoretically (and the producer --
    practically) will be able to determine
    comparative marginal
    productivity of production factors.

    big
    Wieser also pays attention to the division
    productive goods for common and
    specific and different rules
    imputation in each of these cases:
    a specific productive good
    income is imputed on a residual basis.

    This
    Wieser's idea was further developed in
    modern theories of property rights, in
    which the concept of ownership of
    enterprise and, accordingly, the rights to
    residual income is associated with
    the right to dispose of specific
    means of production.

    Not
    only in the section devoted to Wieser, but also
    stands apart in our entire collection
    the last fragment ("75, 76). We have entered
    habit of blaming marginalists for being too
    abstractness of analysis, its abstractness
    from such important public institutions,
    as property, power, etc. Meanwhile
    representatives of the Austrian school
    certainly showed great interest in
    historical and sociological issues.
    The tradition goes back to Menger and his
    analysis of the history of money, but also here
    It was Wieser who contributed the most. His
    ideas about the origin, evolution and
    contradictions between private economic and
    economic order, perhaps especially
    interesting at the present stage of development
    our society.

    Vizer
    far from the optimism of the English
    classics, and above all Smith,
    suggesting harmonic
    harmonization of private and public
    interests through the "invisible hand"
    free competition and
    unconditional condemnation
    private property egoism
    socialist and communist
    literature. He emphasizes that private
    property is inextricably linked to
    economic activity. But private
    property is unthinkable without the powerful
    relationships, dominance and submission.
    Ownership and power are concentrated in
    the hands of economic leaders, in which
    you can easily recognize the prototype of the "entrepreneur" figure
    - the main character of the famous theory
    economic development of I. Schumpeter,
    Wieser's student [see Schumpeter J. A. Theory
    economic development. Moscow: Progress, 1982].

    But
    expansion of private capital, of course,
    pushes capitalist domination beyond
    the limits of economic feasibility and
    entails undesirable public
    contradictions.

    Even
    from such a short passage, the reader can
    get an idea of ​​balance and
    depth of Wieser's analysis not only
    economic, but also social phenomena.

    relevance

    Is there any inconsistency in Menger's reasoning about the order of goods? Perhaps the point is not that goods of different orders satisfy some finite need (for example, the need to eat), but that different goods satisfy fundamentally different, albeit interconnected, needs? The presence of flour, water, fire, etc. satisfies the need to bake bread, which arose as a result of the realization that it is possible to satisfy hunger with bread. The arguments about sowing wheat, for growing crops and obtaining flour are similar. Then the final conclusion should consist in recognizing the object (phenomenon) as a blessing, only if it is directly connected with the satisfaction of needs.

Characteristic features of the Austrian school of economics

Definition 1

The Austrian school is a direction of economic theory in which the concept of "marginal utility" is considered the basis of pricing, but the theory of labor costs is ignored. The emergence of this trend occurred in the 80s of the 19th century in Austria. At the beginning of the 20th century, the most famous representatives of the Austrian school included: G. Gossen, F. Wieser, K. Menger and others. In the 20th century, the direction under consideration was developed by L. Mises, F. Hayek, G. Haberlen.

The goal of the Austrian school of economics was to establish the general types of phenomena of economic activity and to discover the exact laws of economics that ideally characterize economic processes.

Adherents of the Austrian school denied socially necessary expenditures, i.e. the objective basis of pricing, and considered as such a basis the subjective utility of the “limiting copy”, which satisfies the marginal need for a certain product. The valuation of goods depends on the ratio of the stocks of these goods and the needs for them, with an increase in stocks at a certain level of needs, the marginal utility and cost of goods decrease, and with an increase in stocks they increase. Consequently, the value of goods depends on the intensity of needs.

For a long time, the Austrian direction of economic theory was considered in Western economic literature as the driving force of the marginalist revolution, which achieved less success than the others, since it did not have a mathematical apparatus. This understanding of it took shape in the mid-1930s, during the formation of a new Keynesian revolution. However, with the weakening of Keynesianism in the early 1970s and the growing interest in macroeconomic analysis, it turned out that the Austrian school has some significant features that distinguish it from the neoclassical paradigm.

Thus, the Lausanne and Cambridge schools of marginalism proved to be less durable than the Austrian school, which has the most clearly defined appearance.

Methods and basic provisions

Remark 1

The methodological basis of the Austrian school is the abstract-deductive methods of research in political economy, which provide for abstraction from circumstances of a complicating nature.

In the works of K.Menger, the methodological principles of the Austrian direction of economic theory were formulated.

In the Austrian school, the main subject of political economy was considered not the study of the economic relations of people, but the phenomena of economic activity from the standpoint of the minds of economic entities. It was believed that the entire society of the capitalist type is a mechanical set of business entities that are connected only by market relations. The task of political economy, according to theorists of the Austrian trend, was to study the relations of sale and purchase and discover on their basis the eternal, natural laws of social economic development.

The main provisions of the Austrian current:

  • Refusal to use mathematical methods in research;
  • A characteristic feature of most representatives of the school was subjectivism;
  • Focusing on the study of the psychological characteristics of consumer behavior;
  • Emphasis on the structure of capital and variability over time in the study of problems of a macroeconomic nature.

The Austrian school developed the theory of marginal utility. The marginal utility in this case is the value of goods, which depends on the ratio of the stocks of these goods and the needs for it.

The "Menger scale" refers to the main model of marginal utility, which is expressed in an attempt to explain the place of each good on the utility scale and the degree of need for it.

The bourgeois apologetic theory of interest and profit put forward by the Austrian school was in opposition to the Marxist doctrine in the field of surplus value. In this situation, the source of interest was seen in the difference that arises between the highest subjective assessment of a good as a present good and a lower estimate of production means as future goods. According to this theory, labor activity is considered as a future good, which means that at every moment it must be paid below the value of the product produced. Capitalist exploitation is also categorically denied.

The conclusions and theories of the Austrian school served as the beginning of the application of the theory of marginal utility in the development of the bourgeois concept of the socialist type of economy.

Advantages and disadvantages of the Austrian school

Positive aspects of the Austrian School of Economics:

  • Attempts to determine the value of goods and services by their degree of usefulness.
  • Determination of the need to take into account the scarcity of goods when determining their value. This idea was borrowed by representatives of the Austrian school from D. Ricardo.
  • Böhm-Bawerk singled out abstract utility, which is the possible general utility of some goods, independent of their stocks, and specific utility. Specific utility is understood as the real utility of these goods, which, when the need for them is saturated for other subsequent units, will be lower than the previous one.
  • The influence on the cost of goods of fluctuations in supply and demand was determined in connection with the saturation of needs for these goods.
  • Wieser and Jevons substantiated the term "marginal utility", its value.
  • The influence of subjective assessments of individuals on the formation of prices was determined.

The disadvantage of the Austrian direction is the notion that the marginal utility equalization mechanism is carried out only at existing prices and consumer incomes. This indicates that the thesis about calculating prices using the marginal utility of goods, based on subjective estimates dependent on prices, is doubtful.